An explication of the causation between ideas and consequences

Posted on February 17, by Scott Alexander I got many good responses to my Considerations On Cost Disease post, both in the comments and elsewhere. A lot of people thought the explanation was obvious; unfortunately, they all disagreed on what the obvious explanation was.

An explication of the causation between ideas and consequences

Posted on August 10, by Scott Alexander There is an apocryphal story about the visit of the great atheist philosopher Diderot to the Russian court. Diderot was quite the clever debater, and soon this scandalous new atheism thing was the talk of St.

Getting Eulered | Slate Star Codex

Euler said, in a tone of absolute conviction: What is your response to that? Thus was he publicly humiliated, all the Russian Christians got an excuse to believe what they had wanted to believe anyway, and Diderot left in a huff. I feel like I am a lot better at the sorts of things Diderot was good at — philosophy, history, social science, et cetera — than at math.

An explication of the causation between ideas and consequences

Sometimes, I will have a belief that seems pretty well-founded based on the sort of arguments Diderot would have been able to come up with — and someone will spout a bunch of very complicated math at me and tells me it disproves my belief. Otherwise, short of going back to school for ten years and getting a math Ph.

So I think about Diderot a lot because I want to know what to do in this sort of situation. One of my go-to examples here is health insurance and the idea that it is wrong to ever deny someone coverage for anything, no matter how low the probability it will help and how expensive the intervention.

I try to make an argument against that herebut it requires a little math and it would have been very hard to express clearly without it. This is an obvious trade-off. Permament easily-fixable lack of rigor, versus letting anyone with a BA in Mathematics push you around.

The latest people to make a serious academic attempt to prove the existence of God with math, Tim and Lisa McGrew, used Bayesian probabilitya field of math which thanks to the excellent explanations on yudkowsky.

As a result I was able to avoid getting Eulered and write what I think was a pretty devastating rebuttal. But there are other mathematical arguments I find much less tractable.

And by far the most dangerous is statistics. With apologies to Rutherford, all science is statistics or stamp-collecting.

A selected bibliography from mainstream journals with sample quotations

I have tried very hard to outperform most of my famously statistically illiterate profession, but there will always be people far better than I. There will always be people making extremely detailed and Byzantine methodological critiques.

And those people will always be able to present me with arguments that are either ultra-important debunkings of things I believed religiously, or else shameless attempts to Euler me. And I will always have trouble figuring out which ones are which. His basic argument was that proving causation was very very hard which it is and that none of the appropriate statistical work had been displayed in cancer research.

He uses a device to magnify the difference and its importance in the case-control studies by transforming the percentages into observed versus expected figures using a chi-square analysis.

He then suggested that, if the cases had inhaled, 45 lives could have been saved.

Quine, Willard Van Orman: Philosophy of Science | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy

But you know, on a good day I remember my chi-square analyses, I get the difference between case control and cohort studies right, and then I can read an R. On the other hand, Glymour seems to be well respected and intelligent, and he says things like: Factor models assume that observed variables that do not influence one another are independent conditional on all of their common causes, an assumption that is a special case of what Terry Speed has called the Markov condition for directed graphical models.

The rank constraints — of which vanishing tetrads are a special case — used in factor analysis are implied by conditional independencies in factor models, conditional independencies guaranteed by the topological structure of the graph of the model, no matter what values the linear coefficients or factor loadings may have.

To exclude more latent variables when fewer will do, Spearman needed only to assume that the vanishing tetrads do not depend on the constraints on the numerical values of the linear coefficients of factor loadings, but are implied by the underlying causal structure.

It is known that the set of values of linear parameters coefficients and variances that generate probability distributions unfaithful to a directed graph is measure zero in the natural measure on parameter space. Did you realize you could get your Northern Idaho secessionist schools to be tax-subsidized?

You should totally look into that! So I have to ask — am I being informed of deep methodological truths that are being neglected? Or am I being Eulered? The way I try to deal with it in practice is seeing if I can route around the objection. My reaction to the Glymour paper was to try to figure out what it was trying to prove with all its statistics.

I will come out and say it: You are adjusting for an imperfect measurement of the confounders you can think of.

My particular argument was: This is all regressed for the usual things like socioeconomic status.

An explication of the causation between ideas and consequences

That seems vulnerable to exactly the problems you describe.David Hume (—) “Hume is our Politics, Hume is our Trade, Hume is our Philosophy, Hume is our Religion.” This statement by nineteenth century philosopher James Hutchison Stirling reflects the unique position in intellectual thought held by Scottish philosopher David Hume.

Part of Hume’s fame and importance owes to his boldly skeptical approach to a range of philosophical subjects. Individuals come to “know” their own attitudes, emotions, and other internal states partially by inferring them from observations of their own overt behavior and/ .

Discussion on postmodernism and truth. Post modern definition, philosophy quotes and ideas from famous postmodern philosophers (Ayer, Nietzsche, Wittgenstein, Popper, Kuhn, Derrida, Lyotard). On the end of postmodernism and rise of realism of the Wave Structure of Matter.

The Singular Universe and the Reality of Time, by Unger and Smolin, feel in many ways like the most important book I have read in a decade.

Yet it is also one of the frustratingly most flawed books I have ever forced myself to read. [AAA] Atlas of Ancient Archaeology, Jacquetta Hawkes (ed), Barnes and Nobles: [AAF] Answering a Fundamentalist, Albert J. Nevins, M.M., Our Sunday Visitor.

Beyond the Horizon: Chronoschisms and Historical Distance. HANS KELLNER. History and Theory, Theme Issue 50 (December ), Historical distance presents more complex issues than simply evaluating the meaning of the temporal span between a point in the past and some moment present to an observer.

Book Abbreviations